Books

Postmodernist Truth

Here is a story you probably haven't heard, about how a team of American researchers inadvertently introduced a virus into a third world country they were studying..

Advertisement

Postmodernist Truth
info_icon

Here is a story you probably haven't heard, about how a team of American researchers inadvertentlyintroduced a virus into a third world country they were studying. [1] They wereexperts in their field, and they had the best intentions; they thought they were helping the people they werestudying, but in fact they had never really seriously considered whether what they were doing might have illeffects.

It had not occurred to them that a side-effect of their research might be damaging to the fragile ecologyof the country they were studying. The virus they introduced had some dire effects indeed: it raised infantmortality rates, led to a general decline in the health and well-being of women and children, and, perhapsworst of all, indirectly undermined the only effective political force for democracy in the country,strengthening the hand of the traditional despot who ruled the nation.

Advertisement

These American researchers had something to answer for, surely, but when confronted with the devastationthey had wrought, their response was frustrating, to say the least: they still thought that what they weredoing was, all things considered, in the interests of the people, and declared that the standards by whichthis so-called devastation was being measured were simply not appropriate.

Their critics, they contended, were trying to impose "Western" standards in a culturalenvironment that had no use for such standards. In this strange defense they were warmly supported by thecountry's leaders--not surprisingly--and little was heard--not surprisingly--from those who might havebeen said, by Western standards, to have suffered as a result of their activities.

Advertisement

These researchers were not biologists intent on introducing new strains of rice, nor were they agri-businesschemists testing new pesticides, or doctors trying out vaccines that couldn't legally be tested in the U.S.A.They were postmodernist science critics and other multiculturalists who were arguing, in the course of theirprofessional researches on the culture and traditional "science" of this country, that Westernscience was just one among many equally valid narratives, not to be "privileged" in its competitionwith native traditions which other researchers--biologists, chemists, doctors and others--were eager tosupplant.

The virus they introduced was not a macromolecule but a meme (a replicating idea): the idea that sciencewas a "colonial" imposition, not a worthy substitute for the practices and beliefs that had carriedthe third-world country to its current condition.

And the reason you have not heard of this particular incident is that I made it up, to dramatize the issueand to try to unsettle what seems to be current orthodoxy among the literati about such matters. But itis inspired by real incidents--that is to say, true reports. Events of just this sort have occurred in Indiaand elsewhere, reported, movingly, by a number of writers, among them:

Meera Nanda, "The Epistemic Charity of the Social Constructivist Critics of Science and Why the Third World ShouldRefuse the Offer," in N. Koertge, ed., A House Built on Sand: Exposing Postmodernist Myths aboutScience, Oxford University Press, 1998, pp286-311

Advertisement

Reza Afshari, "An Essay on Islamic Cultural Relativism in the Discourse of Human Rights," in Human RightsQuarterly, 16, 1994, pp.235-76.

Susan Okin, "Is Multiculturalism Bad for Women?" Boston Review, October/November, 1997, pp 25-28.

Pervez Hoodbhoy, Islam and Science: Religious Orthodoxy and the Battle for Rationality, London and New Jersey, ZedBooks Ltd. 1991.

My little fable is also inspired by a wonderful remark of E. O. Wilson, in Atlantic Monthly a fewmonths ago: "Scientists, being held responsible for what they say, have not found postmodernismuseful."

Actually, of course, we are all held responsible for what we say. The laws of libel and slander, forinstance, exempt none of us, but most of us--including scientists in many or even most fields--do nottypically make assertions that, independently of libel and slander considerations, might bring harm to others,even indirectly. A handy measure of this fact is the evident ridiculousness we discover in the idea ofmalpractice insurance for . . . . literary critics, philosophers, mathematicians, historians, cosmologists.

Advertisement

What on earth could a mathematician or literary critic do, in the course of executing her professionduties, that might need the security blanket of malpractice insurance? She might inadvertently trip a studentin the corridor, or drop a book on somebody's head, but aside from such outré side-effects, ouractivities are paradigmatically innocuous. One would think. But in those fields where the stakes arehigher--and more direct--there is a longstanding tradition of being especially cautious, and of takingparticular responsibility for ensuring that no harm results (as explicitly honored in the Hippocratic Oath).

Engineers, knowing that thousands of people's safety may depend on the bridge they design, engage infocussed exercises with specified constraints designed to determine that, according to all current knowledge,their designs are safe and sound. Even economists--often derided for the risks they take with otherpeople's livelihoods--when they find themselves in positions to endorse specific economic measures consideredby government bodies or by their private clients, are known to attempt to put a salutary strain on theirunderlying assumptions, just to be safe.

Advertisement

They are used to asking themselves, and to being expected to ask themselves: "What if I'm wrong?"We others seldom ask ourselves this question, since we have spent our student and professional lives workingon topics that are, according both to tradition and common sense, incapable of affecting any lives in waysworth worrying about.

If my topic is whether or not Vlastos had the best interpretation of Plato's Parmenides or how thewool trade affected imagery in Tudor poetry, or what the best version of string theory says about time, or howto recast proofs in topology in some new formalism, if I am wrong, dead wrong, in what I say, the only damageI am likely to do is to my own scholarly reputation.

Advertisement

But when we aspire to have a greater impact on the "real" (as opposed to "academic")world-- and many philosophers do aspire to this today--we need to adopt the attitudes and habits of these moreapplied disciplines. We need to hold ourselves responsible for what we say, recognizing that our words, ifbelieved, can have profound effects for good or ill.

When I was a young untenured professor of philosophy, I once received a visit from a colleague from theComparative Literature Department, an eminent and fashionable literary theorist, who wanted some help from me.I was flattered to be asked, and did my best to oblige, but the drift of his questions about variousphilosophical topics was strangely perplexing to me.

Advertisement

For quite a while we were getting nowhere, until finally he managed to make clear to me what he had comefor. He wanted "an epistemology," he said. An epistemology. Every self-respecting literarytheorist had to sport an epistemology that season, it seems, and without one he felt naked, so he had come tome for an epistemology to wear--it was the very next fashion, he was sure, and he wanted the dernier criin epistemologies. It didn't matter to him that it be sound, or defensible, or (as one might as well say) true;it just had to be new and different and stylish. Accessorize, my good fellow, or be overlooked at the party.

Advertisement

At that moment I perceived a gulf between us that I had only dimly seen before. It struck me at first assimply the gulf between being serious and being frivolous. But that initial surge of self-righteousness on mypart was, in fact, a naive reaction. My sense of outrage, my sense that my time had been wasted by this man'sbizarre project, was in its own way as unsophisticated as the reaction of the first-time theater-goer wholeaps on the stage to protect the heroine from the villain.

"Don't you understand?" we ask incredulously. "It's make believe. It's art. Itisn't supposed to be taken literally!" Put in that context, perhaps this man's quest was not sodisreputable after all. I would not have been offended, would I, if a colleague in the Drama Department hadcome by and asked if he could borrow a few yards of my books to put on the shelves of the set for hisproduction of Tom Stoppard's play, Jumpers.

Advertisement

What if anything would be wrong in outfitting this fellow with a snazzy set of outrageous epistemologicaldoctrines with which he could titillate or confound his colleagues?

What would be wrong would be that since this man didn't acknowledge the gulf, didn't even recognize that itexisted, my acquiescence in his shopping spree would have contributed to the debasement of a preciouscommodity, the erosion of a valuable distinction. Many people, including both onlookers and participants,don't see this gulf, or actively deny its existence, and therein lies the problem.

The sad fact is that in some intellectual circles, inhabited by some of our more advanced thinkers in thearts and humanities, this attitude passes as a sophisticated appreciation of the futility of proof and therelativity of all knowledge claims. In fact this opinion, far from being sophisticated, is the height ofsheltered naiveté, made possible only by flatfooted ignorance of the proven methods of scientifictruth-seeking and their power.

Advertisement

Like many another naif, these thinkers, reflecting on the manifest inability of their methods oftruth-seeking to achieve stable and valuable results, innocently generalize from their own cases and concludethat nobody else knows how to discover the truth either.

Among those who contribute to this problem, I am sorry to say, is, my good friend Dick Rorty. Richard Rortyand I have been constructively disagreeing with each other for over a quarter of a century now. Each of us hastaught the other a great deal, I believe, in the reciprocal process of chipping away at our residual points ofdisagreement. I can't name a living philosopher from whom I have learned more.

Advertisement

Rorty has opened up the horizons of contemporary philosophy, shrewdly showing us philosophers many thingsabout how our own projects have grown out of the philosophical projects of the distant and recent past, whileboldly describing and prescribing future paths for us to take. But there is one point over which he and I donot agree at all--not yet--and that concerns his attempt over the years to show that philosophers' debatesabout Truth and Reality really do erase the gulf, really do license a slide into some form of relativism.

In the end, Rorty tells us, it is all just "conversations," and there are only political orhistorical or aesthetic grounds for taking one role or another in an ongoing conversation.

Advertisement

Rorty has often tried to enlist me in his campaign, declaring that he could find in my own work oneexplosive insight or another that would help him with his project of destroying the illusory edifice ofobjectivity. One of his favorite passages is the one with which I ended my book Consciousness Explained(1991):

It's just a war of metaphors, you say--but metaphors are not "just" metaphors; metaphors are thetools of thought. No one can think about consciousness without them, so it is important to equip yourself withthe best set of tools available. Look what we have built with our tools. Could you have imagined it withoutthem? [p.455]

Advertisement

"I wish," Rorty says, "he had taken one step further, and had added that such tools are allthat inquiry can ever provide, because inquiry is never 'pure' in the sense of [Bernard] Williams' 'project ofpure inquiry.' It is always a matter of getting us something we want." ("Holism, Intrinsicality,Transcendence," in Dahlbom, ed., Dennett and his Critics. 1993.)

But I would never take that step, for although metaphors are indeed irreplaceable tools of thought, theyare not the only such tools. Microscopes and mathematics and MRI scanners are among the others. Yes, anyinquiry is a matter of getting us something we want: the truth about something that matters to us, if all goesas it should.

Advertisement

When philosophers argue about truth, they are arguing about how not to inflate the truth about truth intothe Truth about Truth, some absolutistic doctrine that makes indefensible demands on our systems of thought.It is in this regard similar to debates about, say, the reality of time, or the reality of the past.

There are some deep, sophisticated, worthy philosophical investigations into whether, properly speaking,the past is real. Opinion is divided, but you entirely misunderstand the point of these disagreements if yousuppose that they undercut claims such as the following:

  • Life first emerged on this planet more than three thousand million years ago.

  • The Holocaust happened during World War II.

  • Jack Ruby shot and killed Lee Harvey Oswald at 11:21 am, Dallas time, November 24, 1963.

Advertisement

These are truths about events that really happened. Their denials are falsehoods. No sane philosopher hasever thought otherwise, though in the heat of battle, they have sometimes made claims that could be sointerpreted.

Richard Rorty deserves his large and enthralled readership in the arts and humanities, and in the"humanistic" social sciences, but when his readers enthusiastically interpret him as encouragingtheir postmodernist skepticism about truth, they trundle down paths he himself has refrained from traveling.

When I press him on these points, he concedes that there is indeed a useful concept of truth that survivesintact after all the corrosive philosophical objections have been duly entered. This serviceable, modestconcept of truth, Rorty acknowledges, has its uses: when we want to compare two maps of the countryside forreliability, for instance, or when the issue is whether the accused did or did not commit the crime ascharged.

Advertisement

Even Richard Rorty, then, acknowledges the gap, and the importance of the gap, between appearance andreality, between those theatrical exercises that may entertain us without pretence of truth-telling, and thosethat aim for, and often hit, the truth. He calls it a "vegetarian" concept of truth. Very well,then, let's all be vegetarians about the truth. Scientists never wanted to go the whole hog anyway.

So now, let's ask about the sources or foundations of this mild, uncontroversial, vegetarian concept oftruth.

Right now, as I speak, billions of organisms on this planet are engaged in a game of hide and seek. It isnot just a game for them. It is a matter of life and death. Getting it right, not making mistakes, hasbeen of paramount importance to every living thing on this planet for more than three billion years, and sothese organisms have evolved thousands of different ways of finding out about the world they live in,discriminating friends from foes, meals from mates, and ignoring the rest for the most part.

Advertisement

It matters to them that they not be misinformed about these matters--indeed nothing matters more--but theydon't, as a rule, appreciate this. They are the beneficiaries of equipment exquisitely designed to get whatmatters right but when their equipment malfunctions and gets matters wrong, they have no resources, as a rule,for noticing this, let alone deploring it. They soldier on, unwittingly. The difference between how thingsseem and how things really are is just as fatal a gap for them as it can be for us, but they are largelyoblivious to it.

The recognition of the difference between appearance and reality is a human discovery. A few otherspecies--some primates, some cetaceans, maybe even some birds--shows signs of appreciating the phenomenon of"false belief"--getting it wrong. They exhibit sensitivity to the errors of others, andperhaps even some sensitivity to their own errors as errors, but they lack the capacity for the reflectionrequired to dwell on this possibility, and so they cannot use this sensitivity in the deliberate designof repairs or improvements of their own seeking gear or hiding gear. That sort of bridging of the gap betweenappearance and reality is a wrinkle that we human beings alone have mastered.

Advertisement

We are the species that discovered doubt. Is there enough food laid by for winter? Have I miscalculated? Ismy mate cheating on me? Should we have moved south? Is it safe to enter this cave? Other creatures are oftenvisibly agitated by their own uncertainties about just such questions, but because they cannot actually askthemselves these questions, they cannot articulate their predicaments for themselves or take steps toimprove their grip on the truth. They are stuck in a world of appearances, making the best they can of howthings seem and seldom if ever worrying about whether how things seem is how they truly are.

Advertisement

We alone can be wracked with doubt, and we alone have been provoked by that epistemic itch to seek aremedy: better truth-seeking methods. Wanting to keep better track of our food supplies, our territories, ourfamilies, our enemies, we discovered the benefits of talking it over with others, asking questions, passing onlore.

Tags

    Advertisement

    Advertisement

    Advertisement

    Advertisement

    Advertisement

    Advertisement